There exist numerous cases
of what look like very strong fine-tuning in our universe. Both
fundamental constants and natural laws are arranged in a way that
allows for us to exist. It seems that the probability of all of these
favorable conditions existing by chance is incredibly low. It has
been argued that the probability of you existing in a universe as
fine-tuned as ours is like the chance of you surviving a firing squad
(having 10 or more soldiers firing their rifles at you at close
range). If you survived a firing squad, it is argued, you should
assume there was some purpose involved in this, and that it wasn't
just a lucky accident.
But there is a line of
reasoning which attempts to remove any philosophical implications
from such a situation, a line of reasoning used by those who prefer
to believe that our universe is just an accident. The person who uses
this line of reasoning claims that the fine-tuning of our universe
can by explained by an “observer selection effect.” The reasoning
goes like this:
What type of universe
should we expect to observe? Why, of course, it is only a universe as
fit-for-life as our universe, because that is the only type of
universe that could have observers. So there is an “observer
selection effect” such that all observers find themselves in
universes like ours, and it is not surprising that we exist in a
universe like this.
The
same type of reasoning can be used in regard to the analogy of the
firing squad. The reasoning goes like this:
In regard to that
firing squad analogy, you should not be surprised to find yourself
alive after facing a firing squad. This is because there is an
“observer selection effect” which guarantees that all people who
make observations after facing a firing squad are those who survived
the firing bullets.
Let's
examine such reasoning in detail, first examining the simpler case of
the firing squad.
The
Case of the Firing Squad
When reasoning involving an observer selection effect is
used in regard to firing squads, this “observer selection effect”
is an example of what is called a red herring. A red herring is
an argumentative device in which a person introduces some irrelevant
or less relevant consideration, perhaps to distract you from considering a more
relevant consideration. It may be true that only alive persons could
observe themselves as survivors of a firing squad, but such a fact
doesn't make you the slightest bit more likely to survive a firing
squad. So this “observer selection effect” claim is just a red
herring.
But in regard to statements such as, “You should not
be surprised to find yourself surviving a firing squad, because
that's the only thing you could observe,” is there any validity to
such reasoning? No, there isn't. In this case, it must be remembered
that the case of a non-observation (no observation of anything,
because you're instantly killed) is both a distinct possibility and a
high likelihood. So we should not make the mistake of assuming that
some observation must necessarily occur.
Here are some examples of correct statements and
incorrect statements.
Incorrect statement: Of course, after you finish
high school, you'll end up in Harvard with a nice dorm. Everyone
knows a school like Harvard can afford nice dorms.
Correct statement: No, I almost certainly will
not get such a dorm, because I almost certainly won't get into
Harvard.
Incorrect statement: You can look forward to
marrying a gorgeous starlet, because pretty much the only type of
people who get to be movie starlets are gorgeous people.
Correct statement: No, I almost certainly won't
marry such a starlet, because its way too improbable that I would
marry anyone who is a starlet.
Incorrect statement: You shouldn't be surprised
to survive a firing squad, because the only observation you could
have after facing such a squad would be to observe that you survived.
Correct statement: No, I should be supremely
surprised to survive a firing squad, because if I faced such a squad,
it would be almost certain that I should be instantly killed and have
no further observations.
The most persuasive (but
devious) way to appeal to an observer selection effect is to present
a loaded question, a type of question that makes an unfair
assumption, as in the famous question asking: when did you stop
beating your wife? The loaded question in the case of the firing
squad might be: what should you see around you after facing a firing
squad? Such a question is trickily phrased in a way so that the
answer of survival is already answered. But such trick questions can
always be answered though careful replies, as below.
Incorrect statement: What should you expect to
observe after facing a firing squad? Only that you had survived,
because otherwise you could make no observation.
Correct statement: You should not expect to
observe anything at all after facing a firing squad, because you
should be immediately killed by its bullets.
Another way to clarify the situation of the firing squad
is to do what we may call an exhaustive possibility analysis. When
we do such an analysis, rather than just considering two
possibilities, we will try to consider every possibility. We can
then consider the likelihood of each possibility.
Exhaustive Possibility Analysis for Firing Squad Situation | |
Possibility | Likelihood |
Possibility 1: You immediately die when the bullets kill you, and have no further observations. | Very, very likely (unless your soul survives your death). |
Possibility 2: You survive for a while, with light wounds | Very unlikely |
Possibility 3: You survive for a while, with very heavy wounds that will very soon cause you to die. | Unlikely, but much more likely than Possibility 2. |
Possibility 4: You survive with no wounds, because all of the bullets luckily missed by pure chance. | Incredibly unlikely |
Possibility 5: You die quickly, but observe your dead body when your soul floats out of your body. | Debatable likelihood, but probably far more likely than possibility 4 |
When we consider all of these possibilities, it becomes
clear that any type of “you should not be surprised to find
yourself surviving a firing squad” reasoning (based on an observer
selection effect) is utterly invalid, particularly if “survive the
firing squad” means to end up in pretty good shape when the firing
squad is finished. The most likely possibility is that you should
instantly be killed by the firing squad, and have no observations
after hearing the firing of the guns. The second most likely
possibility is that you should be very heavily wounded after facing
the firing squad, and have only a pitifully short observation before
dying. Possibility 4 (being alive and not wounded) is extremely
unlikely both in the full group of possibilities and also in the
subset of possibilities that include some type of observations by you
after facing the firing squad. It is not at all correct to suggest
that some type of observer selection effect will make it likely that
you will observe yourself in a good state after facing the firing
squad.
The
Case of Habitable Universes
Now let's look at the case of habitable universes. The
reason why I spent so much time discussing firing squads is that the
situation in regard to habitable universes has a strong similarity to
the firing squad situation. Here are the similarities: dying
instantly in the firing squad is similar to a universe that is
uninhabitable; being heavily wounded by the firing squad is similar
to a universe that is just barely habitable; and surviving the
firing squad without any wounds is similar to a universe that has no
shortfalls in regard to habitability, which is the type of universe
we find ourselves in.
Before trying to do an exhaustive possibility analysis,
let us consider the type of “observer selection effect” arguments
made in regard to habitable universes. Below are some examples, along
with corrections.
Incorrect statement: We should not be surprised
to find ourselves living in a finely tuned habitable universe,
because the only type of universes that have observers are finely
tuned universes.
Correct statement: We should be very surprised to
find ourselves living in a finely tuned habitable universe (under
assumptions of randomness), because it is vastly more likely that our
universe should have been uninhabitable and not allowed us to exist
as observers.
Incorrect statement: The fine-tuned nature of
our universe is just as we should expect, because such conditions are
prerequisites of our existence.
Correct statement: Under the assumption of
randomness, the fine-tuned nature of our universe is incredibly
surprising and improbable, given that there is nothing necessary
about our existence.
Now let's try to do an exhaustive possibility analysis
regarding types of universes and what type of observers (if any) they
might have. This will include some interesting possibilities that
are often overlooked.
Exhaustive Possibility Analysis for Observers in Random Universes | |
Possibility | Likelihood |
Possibility 1: The possibility of a random universe that is uninhabitable, and has no observers because life is impossible for one reason or another. | Very likely under assumptions of randomness |
Possibility 2: The possibility of a universe such as ours, with no serious shortfall in regard to habitability | Very unlikely under assumptions of randomness |
Possibility 3: The possibility of a barely habitable universe having some serious shortfalls in regard to habitability, but one in which observers are just barely possible. | Very unlikely, but much more likely than Possibility 2, because the list of conditions that must be met for a barely habitable universe is much shorter than the list of conditions that must be met for a universe such as ours (as argued here). |
Possibility 4: The possibility of a universe in which biological observers cannot appear, but some other types of observers exist – perhaps souls or spirits, or minds of pure energy. | Hard to estimate this likelihood |
Possibility 5: The possibility of a
universe in which biological observers cannot naturally appear,
but one that might be observed by visitors from other universes
|
Hard to estimate this likelihood, but it might be allowed by exotic “wormhole” possibilities |
`When we consider all of these possibilities, it becomes
clear that any type of “you should not be surprised that our
universe is like this” reasoning (based on an observer selection
effect) is utterly invalid, particularly if “a universe like this”
means a universe about as habitable and life-friendly as our
universe. Under assumptions of randomness, the most likely
possibility is that a universe should be uninhabitable and lifeless. The second
most likely possibility is a universe that is just barely habitable, with conditions much harsher than ours (such as a universe with no stars or very few stars or a universe in which either carbon or oxygen was rare). Such a universe is probably at least a thousand times easier to achieve by chance than a universe such as ours (for reasons explained here).
Possibility 2 (a universe as hospitable to life as ours) is extremely
unlikely both in the full group of possibilities and also in the
subset of possibilities that include some type of observers. It is
not at all correct to suggest that some type of observer selection
effect will guarantee that observers only exist in a universe with a
level of fine-tuning as great or almost as great as ours.
The most devious trick of those who evoke an observer
selection effect is to phrase questions such as “What type of universe
should we expect to be living in?” This is a loaded question, one
that has a particular assumption built in to it (like the famous
loaded question which asks when did you stop beating your wife). The
very phrase “should we expect to be living in” presupposes a
universe with an observer.
Incorrect statement: What type of universe
should we expect to be living in? A universe like the one we do live
in, for in no other universe can there be observers.
Correct statement: You are asking a loaded
question if you ask what type of universe should we expect to be
living in, because the phrase “to be living in” presupposes
habitability. Avoiding such a loaded question, we should ask: what
type of universe should we expect our universe to be? Under the
assumption of randomness, the answer is: an uninhabitable universe in
which no observers ever existed. And in the very unlikely case that
our universe happened to be habitable, the most likely case by far
would be that it should be just barely habitable, since the
requirement list for such a universe is much shorter. Such a barely
habitable universe would be much less life-friendly than ours.
“Observer
Selection Effect” Reasoning at the Casino
Let's imagine a hotel casino where there's a special
room called the Big Gamble. You have to pay $10 to get into the room,
where you find a giant laser above your head. There's a lever you
pull to try your luck. After you pull the lever, there is a 99.9999%
chance that the laser will instantly incinerate you, reducing you to
a charred cinder. But there's one chance in a million that you'll
get a jackpot of 5 million dollars. Let's imagine a conversation
between a gambler and a casino employee who gets a commission on all
the people who try the Big Gamble.
Gambler: I was thinking of trying the Big Gamble,
but I'm afraid it will probably just get kill me.
Casino Employee: Go ahead, take a chance!
Gambler: But I just can't see myself winning the
5 million dollars. That would be too surprising.
Casino Employee: Well, I can see you're just
ignoring the “observer selection effect” here.
Gambler: What's that?
Casino Employee: Well, it works like this. If
you don't get incinerated, and win the 5 million dollars, it won't be
surprising at all. Because the only person who could have an
observation after pulling the lever is a person who survived, and won
the 5 million dollars. So you won't be surprised to have survived,
because it's the only kind of observation you could have after
pulling the lever.
Gambler: So it's not such a long shot that I'll
win the 5 million?
Casino Employee: No, when you look at it as I just
discussed, it won't be surprising at all.
Gambler: Okay, I'll make the bet.
The casino employee has used the classic argumentative
technique of the red herring, something that distracts you from
concentrating on what you should be concentrating on, and diverts you
into thinking about some irrelevant distraction. In this case,
whether or not you will be surprised by still being there after
trying the Big Gamble is irrelevant. What is the relevant
consideration is the probability of you winning. The reasoning of
the casino employee is utterly sophistical and fallacious, and when
similar “observer selection effect” reasoning is used on a cosmic scale
when arguing about universes, it is just as irrelevant and misleading
as this casino employee's sales pitch.
No comments:
Post a Comment