For decades the late Stephen
Hawking was the center of a kind of giant hype machine that portrayed
him as the greatest living scientific genius. This hype was unwarranted
for a scientist who never even won a Nobel Prize. Showing admirable
persistence and diligence despite his severe handicaps, Hawking made
some interesting contributions to the study of black holes. But his
thoughts about topics outside of his specialty were often not very
wise.
An example of his dubious
thinking was his “No Boundary Proposal” about the Big Bang, that
the Big Bang was not a boundary in space or time. The problem with
this proposal is that it is the exact opposite of what nature tells
us about the beginning. Everything we have learned about the Big Bang
suggests it is as clear a boundary as you can imagine, a sudden
beginning of time and space.
Hawking also repeatedly warned that machines might take over the world (a fear that is unwarranted for the reasons
discussed here). He repeatedly urged that we need to leave planet Earth (not as good an idea as staying here and making sure that our planet stays in
good health). He repeatedly sung the praises of M-theory, a wildly speculative
theory for which no evidence has ever appeared. He also declared
falsely and unwisely that “philosophy is dead.”
Physicist blogger Ethan
Siegel (whose specialty is cosmology) has a post entitled “The 4
Scientific Lessons Stephen Hawking Never Learned.” He lists one of
these lessons as “Be
humble about your own speculative, unproven ideas.”
He states the following:
This
is a pitfall that has afflicted many of the greatest minds throughout
scientific history: to fall in love with their own fringe scientific
ideas so thoroughly that you tout them with the certainty normally
reserved for verified, validated, robust theories. Hawking's
no-boundary proposal is speculative and unproven, yet Hawking will
often (including in A
Brief History Of Time) speak about it with the same certainty
he'd speak about black holes....Unproven ideas should never be a
substitute for legitimate facts, yet Hawking, in every book he ever
wrote, never tells you when he strays from the
confirmed-and-validated into this speculative realm, particularly
where his own ideas are concerned.
Here Siegel is right on the mark. One of the greatest
problems of modern scientific literature is that writers mix up
speculations and established facts, packaging the whole mixture as
“science.” And so many a dubious proposition and many a doubtful
theory is sold to the public as “science,” as if such things were
well-established. Such failure to distinguish between fact and theory
goes on constantly in the literature of biology, psychology, physics,
and cosmology. When people start a sentence with “Science says,”
half of the time they will refer us to something that has not
actually been established by observations or experiments.
Unfortunately, Siegel himself is often guilty of
exactly this problem of falling in love with his own shaky scientific ideas
so thoroughly “that you tout them with the certainty normally
reserved for verified, validated, robust theories.” We see this
repeatedly in his columns when he refers to the extremely speculative
and very much unverified theory of cosmic inflation as if it
were empirically established science, which it certainly is not. We also
see this repeatedly when Siegel refers to the speculative theory of
dark matter as if it were empirically established, which it is not.
No one has ever directly observed any dark matter. In
the same column that Siegel is criticizing Hawking for speculative
excess, he refers to “everything
we've learned since 1979 about the conditions that set up the Big
Bang.” Nothing of the sort has actually been learned, and we know
nothing whatsoever about any conditions that set up the origin of the
universe.
Not only do we have no
observations about anything occurring any time close to the Big Bang,
but we have no observations (and will never be able to have
any observations) of anything that occurred in the first 300,000 years of the
universe's history. Scientists tell us that it was only at about
300,000 years after the Big Bang that there occurred what is called
the Recombination Era, in which atoms first formed. During the first
300,000 years, particles were so densely packed that all light coming
from those years must have been hopelessly scattered. As a scientific
site tell us:
Because of the presence
of the free electrons, photons were scattered around in all
directions and could not travel far before changing their direction.
Therefore the universe was "opaque".
We
therefore will never be able to get any observations about anything
that happened during the universe's first 300,000 years. The light
from those years was hopelessly jumbled and scrambled by the density
of the matter, as strongly as if you put your Microsoft Word document
through a computer program that might thoroughly scramble its
characters 100,000 times. As we will never be able to make
observations of the universe's state in the first 300,000 years,
all claims about the exact state at the Big Bang (or before it) will
never be claims backed up by observations.
A physicist blogger with a
large following is Lubos Motl, who has been blogging many times a
month since 2004 at his site "The Reference Frame." Motl's blog is a strange collection of physics,
politics, and climate commentary, with many of his opinions being
very dubious (but presented with a large amount of literary skill and
style). Very strangely Motl is for supersymmetry (a theory for which
there is no evidence), but opposed to standard ideas on global
warming (for which there is a great deal of evidence). This is simply an example of how the assertions of a modern scientist may be very largely dependent on the scientist's personal tastes. On the plus
side, I may note that Motl is a good person to have around when
physicists start spouting nonsense about parallel universes, because
he has shown his skill at debunking such speculations.
Another physicist
blogger with some interesting content is Sabine Hossenfelder, who blogs at this site. In
contrast to Motl, she has repeatedly criticized the theory of
supersymmetry, a speculative physics theory. That seems appropriate,
since all signs are that supersymmetry has been a great big waste
of time. Thousands of scientific papers have been written advancing
this ornate speculative theory for which no evidence has been
gathered.
But Hossenfelder has
repeatedly advanced a dubious account as to why physicists
advanced the supersymmetry theory. She has often claimed that
the theory was advanced because physicists find that supersymmetry is
“prettier” or “more beautiful.” Referring to the
supersymmetry theory in a recent post, she says, “I explained many times previously why the conclusions based on naturalness were not predictions, but merely
pleas for the laws of nature to be pretty.”
But it's not correct that
the supersymmetry theory was advanced because physicists had some
great longing for a beautiful or pretty theory. The supersymmetry
theory (a very cluttered affair not at all beautiful) was advanced to
explain away a particular case of fine-tuning in the laws of physics.
Here is how the
wikipedia.org article on supersymmetry explains it:
In the Standard Model,
the electroweak scale receives enormous Planck-scale
quantum corrections. The observed hierarchy between the electroweak
scale and the Planck scale must be achieved with extraordinary fine
tuning. In a supersymmetric
theory, on the other hand, Planck-scale quantum corrections
cancel between partners and superpartners (owing to a minus sign
associated with fermionic loops). The hierarchy between the
electroweak scale and the Planck scale is achieved in a natural
manner, without miraculous fine-tuning.
So the real reason the supersymmetry theory was advanced
was to try to avoid a case of “miraculous fine-tuning.” This is
a much different reason than creating a theory in hopes of making the
laws of nature “be pretty.”
No
evidence has shown up for the supersymmetry theory. So scientists are
stuck with this case of “miraculous fine-tuning” they had hoped
to avoid. In a previous post, Hossenfelder compared this particular
case of fine-tuning to finding a cube balanced on one of it edges.
She says she doesn't believe that “finetuned
parameter values require additional explanation.” In that post she
seems to speak as if she thinks people should not pay much attention
to cases in physics where we find a cosmic balance so delicate that
it's like a cube balanced on one of its edges. I disagree, and think
that such cases (which must have an explanation other than chance)
are weighty cosmic clues we should pay very much attention to.
Postscript: In a recent interview in Scientific American, cosmologist Martin Rees says that the cosmic inflation theory (not to be confused with the more general Big Bang theory) is a "good bet." But we should call things a "good bet" only when we have some probabilistic basis for believing in their likelihood. For example, if you hear a 60-year-old suddenly died in his home, it would be a good bet that he died of a heart problem, because that's the most common cause of sudden deaths in the elderly. But there is no probabilistic basis whatsoever for calling cosmic inflation (a brief burst of exponential expansion of the universe) something likely to have occurred. For such a thing to occur (ending up with a universe like ours) requires so many special conditions and so much fine-tuning that it is wrong to be calling such a theory "a good bet." The theory is better described as a "popular story."
At her blog Sabine Hossenfelder puts the cosmic inflation theory into context:
Theoretical physicists have proposed some thousand ideas for what might have happened in the early universe. There are big bangs and big bounces and brane collisions and string cosmologies and loop cosmologies and all kinds of weird fields that might or might not have done this or that. All of this is pure speculation, none of it is supported by evidence.
Postscript: In a recent interview in Scientific American, cosmologist Martin Rees says that the cosmic inflation theory (not to be confused with the more general Big Bang theory) is a "good bet." But we should call things a "good bet" only when we have some probabilistic basis for believing in their likelihood. For example, if you hear a 60-year-old suddenly died in his home, it would be a good bet that he died of a heart problem, because that's the most common cause of sudden deaths in the elderly. But there is no probabilistic basis whatsoever for calling cosmic inflation (a brief burst of exponential expansion of the universe) something likely to have occurred. For such a thing to occur (ending up with a universe like ours) requires so many special conditions and so much fine-tuning that it is wrong to be calling such a theory "a good bet." The theory is better described as a "popular story."
At her blog Sabine Hossenfelder puts the cosmic inflation theory into context:
Theoretical physicists have proposed some thousand ideas for what might have happened in the early universe. There are big bangs and big bounces and brane collisions and string cosmologies and loop cosmologies and all kinds of weird fields that might or might not have done this or that. All of this is pure speculation, none of it is supported by evidence.
No comments:
Post a Comment